Race to Racism in Enlightenment Thought
Did the concept of race, in modern terms, exist in eighteenth century Europe? When did race, as a theory, come into being and how did the understanding of racial differences turn into racism? Is it valid to apply modern concepts, such as racism, to philosophers and scholars of the eighteenth century? Theses questions have come into the forefront of philosophical debate in regards to many theories presented by Enlightenment thinker such ass Immanuel Kant, David Hume, and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach. The purpose of this paper is to analyze the development of racial classification, the changing meaning of the term “race”, and determine whether the theories presented by these eighteenth century philosophers can be deemed as racism. In order to analyze race, it is necessary to distinguish that this paper will focus on those racial classifications that assign allegedly indisputable negative or positive attributes and characteristics to each racial category.
The first obstacle in analyzing the progression of race is determining what is “race”? The meaning of “race” is constantly interrogated yet rarely understood. Part I of this paper thus examines the origin of the “race” concept. Race can be easily defined in modern terms as a category of persons who share a certain combination of inherited physical traits. The initial separation of humans into “racial” categories was understood to simply reflect inherent biological differences between groups of people. These differences supposedly accounted for natural variances in intelligence, morality, and physical and sexual ability. As such, these “biological” differences were used to justify and explain power differentials between “races” of people. As a biological term, though, race is practically meaningless in modern theory.
.”
Background
It is unclear when the first theories of race as a tool for categorization and social control were first articulated. There is some value to the argument that racial theories separating people into categories, and assigning positive and negative values to those categories, were prevalent by the end of the Middle Ages and during the Renaissance era in England. According to one sociologist, “by the fifteenth century, ‘race, and especially skin color, defined the contours of power relationships…Biological assumptions that were familiar to a nineteenth-century Cuban slave owner would have been recognizable to his fifteenth-century Spanish counterpart.” Further, the noted sociologist Howard Winant has argued that while “the Crusades and the Inquisition and the Mediterranean slave trade were important rehearsals for modern systems of racial differentiation,” that “in terms of scale and inexorability the race concept only began to attain its familiar meanings at the end of the middle ages.”
The noted German philosopher and mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Liebniz defined “race” in genetic terms sometime between 1677 -1686. In presenting the “Egyptian Plan” for world conquest to King Louis XIV of France, Liebniz suggesting creating an army formed from slaves from Africa, Arabia, Canada, New Guinea – Ethiopeans, Negroes, Canadians, and Hurons. Persons from these geographic regions were presented as “semi-beasts” and less than human in large part to “resolve the contradiction between humanistic universalism and Christian particularism – by representing non-Christians as nonhuman”. The racial classification system employed by Liebniz thus relied on religious distinctions (Christian –non-Christian) to justify the enslavement of non-European peoples. Religion would continue to play an important role in the development of racial theory for the next three hundred years.
Primary Sources
The French physician Francios Bernier investigated the basis for human differences in 1684, and categorized the world into four different classes: the Europeans, the Blacks, the Far Easterners, and the Lapps. For each human grouping, Bernier offered crude physical descriptions. Notably, however, Bernier did not imbue each group with positive or negative attributes.
While Liebniz and others may have advanced elementary racial theories dependent in part on interpretations of religious doctrine or geography, it does not appear that a formal racial taxonomy was formulated until 1735. Carolus Linnaeus, a Swedish biological taxonomist, published Systema Naturae which detailed a new classification system for what he deemed to be the three kingdoms of nature: the plant kingdom, the kingdom of stones, and the animal kingdom.[i] Linnaeus separated human beings into four distinct categories described by both color and geographical region: Europeaus (white), Africanus (black), Americanus (red) and Asiatic (yellow).[ii] These categories -- shockingly similar to modern racial classifications – were also by imbued with personal mental and physical characteristics. As the table below demonstrates, Linnaeus believed that whites were gentle, inventive, keen minded and innovative, American Indians were stubborn and angered easily, Asians were avaricious and easily distracted, while Africans were relaxed, negligent, lazy and careless:
Europeaus
Skin(white); build (muscular); hair (long, flowing),eyes (blue); disposition (gentle, and inventive)
Americanus
Skin (reddish); build (erect); hair (black, straight, thick); distinct facial features (wide nostrils); disposition (stubborn and angered easily)
Asiaticus
Skin (sallow; yellow); hair (black); eyes (dark); disposition (avaricious and easily distracted)
Africanus
Skin (black); hair (black; frizzled); skin texture (silky); distinct facial features (nose flat, lips tumid); disposition (relaxed and negligent)
The four part racial division of humans proved to be a lasting and seemingly fundamental principle of racial taxonomy. Some sociologists believe that “the assumption by Linnaeus that mental and moral traits were associated with race was to inform many scientific investigations during the next two hundred years.”
Immanuel Kant, in his “Essay on Race,” proposed that there were four races: the white race, the Negro race, the Hun race (Mongol or Kalmuck), and the Hindu race. Kant later revised his taxonomy by using the following categories: the noble blond (northern Europe); copper red (America); black (Senegambia); and olive-yellow (Asian-Indians).
Kant’s conception of race was clearly biologically based, as he believed that race was a “real degeneration” within a fixed, permanent species. Kant further argued that each racial group had traits that were “unalterably sustained by succeeding generations even under change of ecological setting for protracted periods of time.”[iii] Similar to Linnaeus, Kant also accorded specific physical, mental and moral traits to each racial group. As described in Kant’s essay “On the Different Human Races”:
“(Whites:) contain all natural motive springs in affects and passions, all talents, all predispositions to culture and civilization and can obey as well as rule. They are the only ones who constantly progress toward perfection… Blacks can become disciplined and cultivated but never truly civilized…All races will become exterminated/uprooted (Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves. They thus serve only as slaves) only not the Whites. The stubbornness of Indians in their usages is the reason why they do not melt down with the Whites into a single people. It is not good that they intermix. Spanish in Mexico. On the race of Whites, who have brought about all revolutions in the world. Nomads have only brought about violent revolutions, not ones that sustain themselves… Our (ancient) history of man reliably proceeds only from the white race.”
Kant also maintained that miscegenation between different racial groups would inevitably result in offspring that inherited traits and phenotype equally from both parents.[iv] Kant’s theory of strict miscegenation was short lived and ultimately abandoned, however, when he was first confronted with the ambiguous and unpredictable nature of race – that a mixture of a white person and a “Mongol” did not result, without exception, in a “consistent half-breed.”[v]
The concept of using “race” to account for human variety was a very popular philosophical and scientific project during this time period. Competing with Kant in the effort to promulgate a uniform theory of race based on the teachings of Linnaeus, the German medical doctor and physiologist Johann Friedrich Blumenbach proposed a racial classification scheme that endures to this day. Blumenbach felt that any racial classification scheme would be “very arbitrary indeed both in number and definition,” and was strongly against viewing humans as “different species.” Blumenbach observed that there was “almost insensible and indefinable transition from the pure white skin of the German lady through the yellow, the red, and the dark nations, to the Ethiopian of the very deepest black” and that while people of non-European “races” may be different in color, “as a whole they seem to agree in many things with ourselves.” Rather, Blumenbach believed that differences in complexion and phenotype may be caused by climate and protested against theories of racial superiority or inferiority. It thus is ironic that Blumenbach’s racial ideas would come to be regarded as being among the most influential in the development of modern race theory.
Blumenbach adopted Linnaeus’ division of the world into four racial groups, and in 1781 introduced enduring terminology into the racial lexicon: Caucasian and Mongoloid. Blumenbach settled on the term Caucasian not for any scientific or anthropological reason, but rather felt that white Europeans should be labeled as Caucasian as he felt that the inhabitants of the southern slopes of Mount Caucasus of modern day Georgia were the most beautiful race of people.
The Enlightenment played an important role in the unfolding of race and racism in Europe. The Enlightenment of the 1700s marked an intellectual shift defined primarily by an enthusiasm for organizing and understanding the world through secular reason. This shift coincided with a geopolitical expansion that made Europeans far more cognizant of human differences throughout the world. The Enlightenment impulse drove Europeans to categorize the diversity of life on Earth, especially in the arrangement of human difference. The first to use the term race to connote categories of people was François Bernier in 1684. For Bernier, race was entirely a physical distinction: people who looked different were clearly members of different races.
Others took up racial studies in an attempt to identify the exact number of races in the world. The most definitive efforts of the era were Carolus Linnaeus's 1735 four-part division of humanity ("White European, Red American, Dark Asiatic and Black Negro") and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach's 1776 division into five races ("Caucasians [a term he introduced], Mongolians, Ethiopians, Americans, and Malays"). Others countered that there were some thirty to eighty races. How thinkers distinguished between races mattered less than what united each of their approaches. Each definition used physical features as the primary measure of human difference. This physical basis relied on a hierarchical notion of proper development that was rooted in the Enlightenment's exaltation of the classical world as the epitome of beauty and physical form The qualitative differences between races arose when enlightened theorists sought to explain the source of human differences and the varieties of societies that Europeans were encountering.
Charles-Louis de Secondat, baron de Montesquieu, was one of the first, in his Spirit of the Laws (1748), to present human history as composed of stages, introducing the idea that races of people had developed their own legal and political systems rooted in their climate and their temperament, or, as he called them, their race. Politics and race ran together; different races created the political systems only they were capable of creating. Other thinkers, like Immanuel Kant in his On the Different Races of Man (1775), aligned peoples' characters with their physical appearance. Now, behavior and appearance ran together; one could assess peoples' potential solely by looking at them. For the most part, however, Kant, like others at this time, used the term race loosely, without any real concern for scientific precision or exactness. Such systems provided a vocabulary for distinguishing between people based on (supposedly) natural differences that determined people's abilities and justified differing applications of rights and liberties.
Secondary Sources
The racial theories of Blumenbach and other philosophers rose to special importance during the Age of Enlightenment. The Enlightenment period is important to understanding the history of the race concept, given that an understanding of race reflects in large part an understanding of how society accounts for human differences and similarities. The Aristotelian notion that inequality was the foundation of the natural order of things, as reflected in the concept of a “great chain of being,” popularized the notion that some people were naturally inferior to others. As such, “it was but a small step to apply the same concept of hierarchical ordering within the ranks of humankind.”
Accordingly, the early theories of race and racial merit provided by Linnaeus, Kant, Blumenbach and others soon became the basis for acceptable science during the Enlightenment period. The Enlightenment philosophies of rationality and empiricism, developed to help understand the larger world, unsurprisingly were applied to the smaller world of racial science. As David Goldberg has stated:
The emergence of independent scientific domains of anthropology and biology defined a classificatory order of racial groupings – subspecies of Homo sapiens – along correlated physical and cultural matrixes. Empiricism encouraged the tabulation of perceivable differences between peoples and from this it deduced their natural differences. Rationalism proposed initial innate distinctions (especially mental ones) to explain the perceived behavioural disparities.
The Enlightenment philosophies engendered a shift from a pre-modern understanding of human identity rooted in religion and the preservation of noble wealth through biological understandings of lineage, to an understanding of human identity rooted in race. That said, Kenan Malik has thoughtfully explained that the Enlightenment concepts of reason, rationality and the scientific method, by themselves, do not give rise to understanding human difference in terms of race. Rather, the Enlightenment beliefs in reason, empiricism and human equality were applied to justify existing inequality in terms of purported “racial” difference.
Nicholas Hudson explains in his article, From “Nation” to “Race”: The Origin of Racial Classification in Eighteenth Century Thought”, how the definition of race has emerged from earlier terms of “lineage”. Hudson proceeds to explain how the idea of race emerged sometime during the eighteenth century with philosophers like Hume and scientists like Linnaeus. He believes that the factors which caused the transformation from “Nation” to “Race” was do to scientific developments as well as economic requirements.
My final secondary source is by Eric Morton. His article, Race and Racism in the Works of David Hume, provides an in depth look at the philosophical theories of David Hume and the contradictory nature of Hume’s philosophies.
The Enlightenment belief in universal human nature and the natural rights idea of social equality necessarily understood social inequality and human difference as being irrelevant artificial expressions of feudal, monarchist social structures. Thus the Enlightenment philosopher David Hume stated, “it is universally acknowledged that there is great uniformity among the acts of men, in all nations and ages, and human nature remains still the same in its principles and operations.” So then what could have led Hume to later state that “I am apt to suspect the negroes to be naturally inferior to the whites” and that “[s]uch a uniform and constant difference [between ‘negroes’ and ‘whites’] could not happen… if nature had not made an initial distinction between these breeds of men”? What led Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment thinkers to develop a racially-based “exception” to this general principle of universal human equality?
The call for universal rights by non-propertied social classes clashed with the very bourgeoisie notions of capitalism and the free market that displaced the old order of monarchy and feudalism. The inherent inequality that stemmed from the private ownership of property led Adam Smith and other thinkers to believe that there had to be limits and exceptions to “universal equality” in order to protect the “natural” rights of propertied classes. Indeed, there had been a long standing pre-racial feudal tradition to organize society according to kinship and “blood ties.” Entitlement to political power and class position was determined in large part upon patrilineal descent premised on the transmission of a “common substance” from father to son.
Thus early theories of “race” ostensibly sought to explain class distinctions in a post-feudal society. The writings of Count Arthur Gobineau in Essays on the Inequality of Races, demonstrate this evolving viewpoint:
It has already been established that every social order is founded upon three original classes, each of which represents a racial variety: the nobility, a more or less accurate reflection of the conquering race; the bourgeoisie composed of mixed stock coming close to the chief race; and the common people who live in servitude or at least in a very depressed position. These last belong to a lower race which came about in the south through miscegenation with the negroes and in the north with Finns.
Race theory thus filled the void left by feudal hierarchy in explaining class distinctions, and reconciled the unequal treatment of certain groups of people with liberalism’s embrace of universal equality. Considering the history of such “racializing”, we should, at least, see that it is by no means a permanent or unavoidable way of understanding human kind. Late Renaissance perceptions of the other, while certainly distorted by religious prejudice and contempt for “savagery”, lacked a real foundation in racial classification. The racial world view that slowly emerged in the eighteenth century took shape under the social and intellectual forces of that time—an expanding imperial order, a new science, and the creation of a new, secular myth of human origin and human nature. In terms of the whether the philosophies presented in this paper can be deemed racist, I believe the answer to be no. It is obvious to twentieth and twenty-first century scholars to read these theories and be disgusted by what was written. The fact remains that at this time to be superior t another being was not just based on race but was also based on class. The society in which these theories were developed was just beginning to explore the world outside of Europe and their new discoveries were perplexing and needed immediate explanation. This does not mean that they understood the wrong in which they were committing. The contradictory statements made by each philosopher prove that they believed in equality but could not comprehend the external differences between men of different continents.
Bibliography
Blumenbach, Johann Friedrich. On the Natural Varieties of Mankind. reprint of 1856 English translation, New York: Bergman Publishers, 1969
Buffon, George Louis Leclerc, Comte de. A Natural History, General and Particular. Containing the History and Theory of the Earth, A General History of Man, the Brute Creation, Vegetable, Minerals, &c., &c.. trans. from the French by William Smellie, 2 nd ed., v. III, The Natural History of Man, sec. IX, Of the Varieties of the Human Species, London: Richard Evans; Edinburgh: John Bourne, 1817.
Gobineau, Arthur (Count Joseph Arthur de Gobineau) and Adrian Collins. [1853-55] 1983. The Inequality of Human Races. Second edition, reprint. Torrance, California: Noontide Press.
Hume, David. Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1988.
--------. The Letters of David Hume. ed. by J. Y. T. Greig. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932.
--------. “Of National Characters,” The Philosophical Works of David Hume. Including all the essays, and exhibiting the more important alterations and corrections in the successive editions published by the author. v. III, Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1854.
--------. A Treatise of Human Nature. Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1992.
Kant, Immanuel. Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime, trans. by John T. Goldthwait. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1960.
Linnaeus, (Carl von Linne). A General System of Nature Through the Three Grand Kingdoms of Animals, Vegetable, and Minerals. London: Lackington, Allen and Company, 1806, (7 volumes) vol. 1. 37
Malik, Kenan The Meaning of Race: Race, History and Culture in Western Society, Palgrave / New York University Press, 1996
Morton, Eric (2002). RACE AND RACISM IN THE WORKS OF DAVID HUME. Journal on African Philosophy: 1, 1.
Sunday, April 19, 2009
Saturday, March 28, 2009
African cultures came into western purview with the onset of European imperialism and subsequent colonialism. Ironically, while the colonialists described the highly stylized and generally abstract art forms of this region as “primitive”, Western society, in particular the Parisians, came to appreciate the powerful originality of non-Western art. Parisians began to glorify “exotic” cultures for their freedom from the taint of civilization. The appeal of the primitive constituted a rebellion in the first decades of the twentieth century to challenge all that preceded it.
Avant-garde artitsts turned their backs on academic standards and the tyranny of representation. They pioneered an authentic “stripped down” style that evoked rather than described experience. They found their inspiration in the arts of the non-Western cultures; primitivism, abstraction, and experimentation were hallmarks of the modern revolt against convention and tradition. The new style was inspired by the arts of Africa which were featured in Paris art exhibitions and theatrical productions. Arts from Africa helped Parisians to discover the significance of art as a fetish, that is, as the palpable embodiment of potent magical forces.
The erotic nature of African art was pushed onto the African culture by Europeans as well. Africans were perceived as exotic, a quality and characteristic that French intellectuals, artists, and society in general wanted exposure to. The term negrophilia is one which is often applied to describe this time in Paris; A time when Parisians fell in love with black culture. The French became absorbed but the exotic nature of African culture and artists such as Josephine Baker. The new culture allowed Europeans to escape from their cultural norms into a new exotic world. Although, this time seemed to be one of cultural acceptance it was not. Europeans still believed Africans to be different and unusual and most of the artistic expression, such as music, was changed by the black performers in order to please Europeans. Africans and their culture were still seen as foreign and primitive, stereotypes were still applied and expectations continued to be set in place. The acceptance of African culture stemmed simply from the fact that Europeans wanted an escape from their lives and found that escape in the culture of Africa.
Avant-garde artitsts turned their backs on academic standards and the tyranny of representation. They pioneered an authentic “stripped down” style that evoked rather than described experience. They found their inspiration in the arts of the non-Western cultures; primitivism, abstraction, and experimentation were hallmarks of the modern revolt against convention and tradition. The new style was inspired by the arts of Africa which were featured in Paris art exhibitions and theatrical productions. Arts from Africa helped Parisians to discover the significance of art as a fetish, that is, as the palpable embodiment of potent magical forces.
The erotic nature of African art was pushed onto the African culture by Europeans as well. Africans were perceived as exotic, a quality and characteristic that French intellectuals, artists, and society in general wanted exposure to. The term negrophilia is one which is often applied to describe this time in Paris; A time when Parisians fell in love with black culture. The French became absorbed but the exotic nature of African culture and artists such as Josephine Baker. The new culture allowed Europeans to escape from their cultural norms into a new exotic world. Although, this time seemed to be one of cultural acceptance it was not. Europeans still believed Africans to be different and unusual and most of the artistic expression, such as music, was changed by the black performers in order to please Europeans. Africans and their culture were still seen as foreign and primitive, stereotypes were still applied and expectations continued to be set in place. The acceptance of African culture stemmed simply from the fact that Europeans wanted an escape from their lives and found that escape in the culture of Africa.
Monday, March 16, 2009
HST 498 - Essay 6 - Newhard
Since the birth of civilization, no age has broken with tradition more radically or more self-consciously than the twentieth century. In part, the modernist break with the past represents the willful rejection of former values but it also registers the revolutionary effects of science on all aspects of life. Unfortunately, a new reason for racism was born from the new scientific “knowledge” obtained during this century. There are two relatively clear reasons for the steadfast insistence on subjugating the observed African to a simplified stereotypical image of “other”. The first concerns the nature of we/they relationships. The relationship itself requires that we identify the characteristics that distinguish us from them. The second factor, that influenced twentieth century Europeans, is the failure to distinguish between biological and cultural classifications. Twentieth century Europeans embraced a new theory called eugenics which was the belief that biology could determine the superiority and inferiority of different racial and social groups. In other words, Eugenics was scientific racism. Eugenics used scientific findings and methods to validate racist attitudes. This theory was very popular in England and Germany during the early twentieth century due to both countries desire for domination.
In England, the main reason behind the segregation and discrimination of Africans was due to tension within the middle class. Stone wrote, “the middle class in Britain felt trapped between a still dominant old elite and an emerging working class clamoring for rights.”(Stone 2) This in turn created a need to prove English middle-class superiority and the opportunity was provided by the theory of Eugenics and the presence of Africans. Europeans believed that Africans were not hard working, poor, and unintelligent. In addition, it was believed that Africans were barbaric creatures who killed woman after intercourse (Bush 210). These factors allowed Europeans to feel superior to Africans but at the same time elevated fears that Africans posed a threat to the European way of life. Therefore, the German’s desire for preservation of racial purity was justified.
Germany took a different approach to the implementation of the theory of Eugenics. In Germany at this time, “pure” German blood was the most important and powerful weapon Germany had. Therefore, any tainting of German blood would be catastrophic. The fear of African contamination also stemmed from the presence of French African soldiers in Germany after the Vienna conference. German people began to fear and despise African people fro their intrusion of Germany. In addition, both Germans and British believed that the interbreeding of Africans with their superior race would cause a decline in their superiority and sought out to inhibit reproduction between Europeans and Africans. This in turn resulted in the belief of European superiority and African inferiority. Africans were thought of as a different species of being. Africans were of a race unworthy and unable to join European culture. They were therefore cast out as “others”.
In England, the main reason behind the segregation and discrimination of Africans was due to tension within the middle class. Stone wrote, “the middle class in Britain felt trapped between a still dominant old elite and an emerging working class clamoring for rights.”(Stone 2) This in turn created a need to prove English middle-class superiority and the opportunity was provided by the theory of Eugenics and the presence of Africans. Europeans believed that Africans were not hard working, poor, and unintelligent. In addition, it was believed that Africans were barbaric creatures who killed woman after intercourse (Bush 210). These factors allowed Europeans to feel superior to Africans but at the same time elevated fears that Africans posed a threat to the European way of life. Therefore, the German’s desire for preservation of racial purity was justified.
Germany took a different approach to the implementation of the theory of Eugenics. In Germany at this time, “pure” German blood was the most important and powerful weapon Germany had. Therefore, any tainting of German blood would be catastrophic. The fear of African contamination also stemmed from the presence of French African soldiers in Germany after the Vienna conference. German people began to fear and despise African people fro their intrusion of Germany. In addition, both Germans and British believed that the interbreeding of Africans with their superior race would cause a decline in their superiority and sought out to inhibit reproduction between Europeans and Africans. This in turn resulted in the belief of European superiority and African inferiority. Africans were thought of as a different species of being. Africans were of a race unworthy and unable to join European culture. They were therefore cast out as “others”.
Monday, March 2, 2009
The European colonization of Africa began in the late 19th century. Contact between Europeans and Africans had been established centuries before the 19th century with the Trans-Atlantic slave trade, but Europeans had not imposed official rule over Africa until this time. There have been many reasons put forth in an attempt to explain the beginnings of European imperialism of Africa. Reasons such as, economic possibilities and development, political power, cultural beliefs, and religious education have been used to explain this European conquest but the fact remains that European imperialism was intentional and motivated by national-preservation.
Many scholars agree that one of the main reasons behind the European conquest of Africa was economic. Africa was a continent of vast wealth and contained many raw materials such as cotton, rubber, ivory, and minerals which were not found in Europe. The industrial revolution in Europe caused the need for metals and raw materials like copper and tin for manufacturing which Europeans found in vast abundance throughout Africa. In addition, Africa became a new market for Europeans to sell their manufactured goods. This leads to the second reason behind European imperialism that has been presented; the desire for political power. During this time, it was the country who owned the most land and the best trade routes which possessed the most power. Africa was a prime location for European countries seeking more power due to its abundance of undeveloped land and the Suez Canal, which became an important trade route and important addition to any European nation’s supremacy who controlled it. In addition, the European belief in their own cultural and racial superiority made Europeans feel like it was their duty to develop the uncivilized African cultures. This also caused a missionary movement by Catholics to bring Christianity to the African countries. The belief was that the people of Africa were uncultured and of a lower intelligence than Europeans and therefore should be ruled by the more intelligent Europeans. This was in a sense Social Darwinism, where only the strong survive and dominate the weak.
No matter what the justification, each reason is based on national preservation and European domination. Europeans colonized Africa within twenty five years, 1885 to 1910, even though they had been financially involved with Africa for centuries. This evidence and the evidence provided above, shows that European imperialism was a more planned out conquest rather than a spontaneous series of events. Once Europeans saw the opportunity for economic growth, they went full force into economic, political, and cultural domination of Africa in order to ensure their places at the top.
Many scholars agree that one of the main reasons behind the European conquest of Africa was economic. Africa was a continent of vast wealth and contained many raw materials such as cotton, rubber, ivory, and minerals which were not found in Europe. The industrial revolution in Europe caused the need for metals and raw materials like copper and tin for manufacturing which Europeans found in vast abundance throughout Africa. In addition, Africa became a new market for Europeans to sell their manufactured goods. This leads to the second reason behind European imperialism that has been presented; the desire for political power. During this time, it was the country who owned the most land and the best trade routes which possessed the most power. Africa was a prime location for European countries seeking more power due to its abundance of undeveloped land and the Suez Canal, which became an important trade route and important addition to any European nation’s supremacy who controlled it. In addition, the European belief in their own cultural and racial superiority made Europeans feel like it was their duty to develop the uncivilized African cultures. This also caused a missionary movement by Catholics to bring Christianity to the African countries. The belief was that the people of Africa were uncultured and of a lower intelligence than Europeans and therefore should be ruled by the more intelligent Europeans. This was in a sense Social Darwinism, where only the strong survive and dominate the weak.
No matter what the justification, each reason is based on national preservation and European domination. Europeans colonized Africa within twenty five years, 1885 to 1910, even though they had been financially involved with Africa for centuries. This evidence and the evidence provided above, shows that European imperialism was a more planned out conquest rather than a spontaneous series of events. Once Europeans saw the opportunity for economic growth, they went full force into economic, political, and cultural domination of Africa in order to ensure their places at the top.
Sunday, February 22, 2009
Essay 4 - Newhard
The age of Enlightenment, as the eighteenth century is often called, was a time of rising optimism. Educated Europeans envisioned themselves as the most civilized people in history. Reason, they optimistically predicted, would dispel the mists of human ignorance, superstition, and prejudice. Although enlightenment thinkers envisioned a human race filled with progressive ideas and which embraced principles of reason, many factors served as obstacles to the realization of the vision. Ignorance, for example, the foundation of bias and unwitting prejudice, clouded the perceptions and judgments of some of the most educated men of this time. In human terms, the most glaring evidence of the failure of the Enlightenment was the perpetuation of the slave trade, which despite much condemnation, flourished until the mid nineteenth century.
African children were often kidnapped by unscrupulous natives who profited handsomely by selling their captives to white slave traders. The fate of the African slave who survived the perilous “Middle Passage” was a life of unspeakable suffering. A first-hand account of this inhumane system is central to the autobiographical narrative of Olaudah Equiano who was born in the West African Kingdom of Benin and kidnapped and enslaved at the age of eleven. Both as a slave and after his release from slavery in 1766, Equiano traveled widely. For Olaudah Equiano, the concept of freedom had many definitions. While Olaudah was a child, being transported from ship to ship and master to master, his understanding of freedom came from the memories of his childhood. Soon, Olaudah began to understand the way of the Western world and his concept of freedom changed; he now saw freedom as being incorporated into Western culture. Olaudah eventually purchased his “freedom” from his master in 1766 but he did not feel completely liberated. In order for Equiano and other Africans to be completely “free” they desired to be accepted by whites by conforming to white society. In order to achieve this concept of freedom, Olaudah and other Africans believed that education and Christianity were the keys.
Unfortunately, the material benefit of slavery outweighed the moral indecency to many of the English in the eighteenth century. Although many English citizens believed the treatment of the African slaves to be unnecessary and the Christian church convinced the courts to abolish slavery, African men and women were never equal to those of white English society. The planters particularly, were against the abolishment of slavery and the missionary action to teach the slaves about Christianity. They believed that the African slaves were not intelligent enough to comprehend Christian beliefs and that they did not have the intelligence to comprehend their religion. The planters also feared that if the slaves were taught about Christianity, they would see themselves as equals to the planters and other Christian believers. On the other side of the argument, those who wanted to teach Christianity to the slaves believed that if the slaves were taught about Christianity, they would become more obedient and better workers for the planters. Either way both sides of the argument were against the freedom and equality of the Africans.
African children were often kidnapped by unscrupulous natives who profited handsomely by selling their captives to white slave traders. The fate of the African slave who survived the perilous “Middle Passage” was a life of unspeakable suffering. A first-hand account of this inhumane system is central to the autobiographical narrative of Olaudah Equiano who was born in the West African Kingdom of Benin and kidnapped and enslaved at the age of eleven. Both as a slave and after his release from slavery in 1766, Equiano traveled widely. For Olaudah Equiano, the concept of freedom had many definitions. While Olaudah was a child, being transported from ship to ship and master to master, his understanding of freedom came from the memories of his childhood. Soon, Olaudah began to understand the way of the Western world and his concept of freedom changed; he now saw freedom as being incorporated into Western culture. Olaudah eventually purchased his “freedom” from his master in 1766 but he did not feel completely liberated. In order for Equiano and other Africans to be completely “free” they desired to be accepted by whites by conforming to white society. In order to achieve this concept of freedom, Olaudah and other Africans believed that education and Christianity were the keys.
Unfortunately, the material benefit of slavery outweighed the moral indecency to many of the English in the eighteenth century. Although many English citizens believed the treatment of the African slaves to be unnecessary and the Christian church convinced the courts to abolish slavery, African men and women were never equal to those of white English society. The planters particularly, were against the abolishment of slavery and the missionary action to teach the slaves about Christianity. They believed that the African slaves were not intelligent enough to comprehend Christian beliefs and that they did not have the intelligence to comprehend their religion. The planters also feared that if the slaves were taught about Christianity, they would see themselves as equals to the planters and other Christian believers. On the other side of the argument, those who wanted to teach Christianity to the slaves believed that if the slaves were taught about Christianity, they would become more obedient and better workers for the planters. Either way both sides of the argument were against the freedom and equality of the Africans.
Monday, February 16, 2009
Contrary to the “freedom principle”, by the mid eighteenth century thousands of Africans had been forced to migrate to France as slaves. The idea that France had no slaves is based upon this "freedom principle" in which all citizens of France and any person who set foot on French soil was automatically deemed free. The fact that France had many colonies that employed the institution of slavery proves the hypocrisy of this principle and shows the labyrinth of resistance to change by the French government that stifled attempts at reform. In addition, this principle was the basis for the fight against slavery in France. There are two laws that show the hypocritical nature of the government in regards to the freedom of slaves, the Code Noir and the Declaration of December.
The Code Noir sought to regulate slaves both in colonies and those traveling with masters to France. The code required baptism of slaves in an effort to police the flow of slaves brought into France. The hypocrisy of this code lies in the fact that it did not conform to the common law of the “freedom principle” which stated that slaves could be freed once they landed in the ports of France. The reason for this hypocrisy was the idea that freeing a slave was essentially property loss. The Edict of October 1716 was created in order to fix this problem of property loss by allowing masters to bring slaves to France without giving them the ability of gaining their freedom. The Edict of October 1716 was not registered in the Parliament of Paris or the Admiralty Court of France which for all intents and purposes made it invalid. The Admiralty Court also gave slaves the ability to bring suit against owners which caused an increase in the number of lawsuits brought against slave owners and therefore another problem which needed to be resolved. Therefore, The Declaration of December was established which sought to prevent slaves from petitioning for freedom and attempted to limit the amount of slaves entering France.
The motives behind those who attempted to help free the slaves were based on both principles and personal reasons. Some lawyers were sympathetic to the atrocity of enslavement and truly wanted to provide slaves with their natural right of freedom. Other lawyers were motivated by the benefits which came with taking these cases such as money and furthering their own careers. The various laws that attempted to regulate the status and freedom of slaves in France demonstrate the intent of those making the laws. The law makers who attempted to help free Africans were not intending to free all slaves nor were they condemning the institution of slavery, instead they were attempting to regulate the slaves which were in France as well as attempting to prevent the migration of more slaves into France.
The Code Noir sought to regulate slaves both in colonies and those traveling with masters to France. The code required baptism of slaves in an effort to police the flow of slaves brought into France. The hypocrisy of this code lies in the fact that it did not conform to the common law of the “freedom principle” which stated that slaves could be freed once they landed in the ports of France. The reason for this hypocrisy was the idea that freeing a slave was essentially property loss. The Edict of October 1716 was created in order to fix this problem of property loss by allowing masters to bring slaves to France without giving them the ability of gaining their freedom. The Edict of October 1716 was not registered in the Parliament of Paris or the Admiralty Court of France which for all intents and purposes made it invalid. The Admiralty Court also gave slaves the ability to bring suit against owners which caused an increase in the number of lawsuits brought against slave owners and therefore another problem which needed to be resolved. Therefore, The Declaration of December was established which sought to prevent slaves from petitioning for freedom and attempted to limit the amount of slaves entering France.
The motives behind those who attempted to help free the slaves were based on both principles and personal reasons. Some lawyers were sympathetic to the atrocity of enslavement and truly wanted to provide slaves with their natural right of freedom. Other lawyers were motivated by the benefits which came with taking these cases such as money and furthering their own careers. The various laws that attempted to regulate the status and freedom of slaves in France demonstrate the intent of those making the laws. The law makers who attempted to help free Africans were not intending to free all slaves nor were they condemning the institution of slavery, instead they were attempting to regulate the slaves which were in France as well as attempting to prevent the migration of more slaves into France.
Monday, February 9, 2009
HST 498 - Essay 2
Two factions confronted each other in British parliament during the early eighteenth century; the Whigs and the Tories. They were the only political parties in Britain until the mid 19th century and their opposite beliefs helped to develop the idea of a left and right wings of politics. The Whigs stood for political and economic liberalism, a strong parliament, and religious tolerance, the Tories defended the rights of the Anglican Church and crown. After the Industrial revolution, the emerging middle class elicited reactionary policies from the aristocratic Tories who dominated the parliament. The basic problem in the eighteenth century and early nineteenth century was the partition of power. The old aristocratic members of parliament were adamant in refusing to yield its control over to the state. Some liberal Tories however, felt that the public protests of injustice had validity and responded by passing legislation reforming laws, especially in the debate of anti- slavery. The early abolitionist movement dates from the late eighteenth century and continued into the early nineteenth century. The movement included campaigners from all member of society; women, black activists, working men, church leaders, and members of parliament from both parties. All of those involved in the movement to abolish slavery had their reasons for their support of the faction and their own role in finally abolishing slavery in Britain.
For the most part, the early opponents focused on the immorality of the slave trade. Their beliefs stemmed from Enlightenment thinkers who demanded a review of the methods of government on the basis of reason and an idea of equality of all mankind. The main groups involved in these ideologies were women, Quakers, and slaves. These groups brought petitions to the parliament, staged protests and boycotts, and were extremely successful in gaining support for their cause. Their greatest alliances came from members of parliament who were able to bring the issue of the morality of the slave trade to the courts. The members of these groups believed in a system of equality and saw the slave trade and slavery as evil and unchristian. Their uprisings caused members of parliament to look at the system of slavery and reevaluate it. The second movement of anti-slavery came from an economic standpoint. The politicians, merchants, and economists began to argue that the slave trade was too costly and the economic benefit no longer existed. Therefore, if the cost outweighed the benefit the slave system was no longer worth the effort.
In either case, whether the cause for the abolishment of slavery was humanitarian or economic, the fact remains that people from all parts of society, men and women, whites and blacks, Whigs and Tories, came together to destroy a system that was cruel and unnecessary;
For the most part, the early opponents focused on the immorality of the slave trade. Their beliefs stemmed from Enlightenment thinkers who demanded a review of the methods of government on the basis of reason and an idea of equality of all mankind. The main groups involved in these ideologies were women, Quakers, and slaves. These groups brought petitions to the parliament, staged protests and boycotts, and were extremely successful in gaining support for their cause. Their greatest alliances came from members of parliament who were able to bring the issue of the morality of the slave trade to the courts. The members of these groups believed in a system of equality and saw the slave trade and slavery as evil and unchristian. Their uprisings caused members of parliament to look at the system of slavery and reevaluate it. The second movement of anti-slavery came from an economic standpoint. The politicians, merchants, and economists began to argue that the slave trade was too costly and the economic benefit no longer existed. Therefore, if the cost outweighed the benefit the slave system was no longer worth the effort.
In either case, whether the cause for the abolishment of slavery was humanitarian or economic, the fact remains that people from all parts of society, men and women, whites and blacks, Whigs and Tories, came together to destroy a system that was cruel and unnecessary;
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)